The monotone class theorem, and closely related -system lemma, are simple but fundamental theorems in measure theory, and form an essential step in the proofs of many results. General measurable sets are difficult to describe explicitly so, when proving results in measure theory, it is often necessary to start by considering much simpler sets. The monotone class theorem is then used to extend to arbitrary measurable sets. For example, when proving a result about Borel subsets of
, we may start by considering compact intervals and then apply the monotone class theorem. I include this post on the monotone class theorem for reference.
We start with some definitions. Given a collection of subsets of a set
, we use the notation
for the complement of
.
Definition 1 Let
be a set. Then, a collection
of subsets of
is a
-system if and only if
for all
.
- algebra if and only if
.
for all
.
for all
.
- monotone class if and only if
for all increasing sequences
.
for all decreasing sequences
.
- d-system (or Dynkin system, or
-system) if and only if
.
for all
in
.
for all increasing sequences
.
-algebra if and only if
.
for all
.
for all sequences
.
In short, we can say that a -system is closed under pairwise intersections, an algebra is closed under finite set operations, a monotone class is closed under increasing and decreasing limits, a d-system is closed under increasing limits, taking differences with a subset, and contains the whole space, and a
-algebra is closed under countable set operations.
There are various simple relations between the definitions given above.
Lemma 2
- every algebra is a
-system.
- every d-system is a monotone class.
- every
-algebra is a
-system, an algebra, a monotone class and a d-system.
Proof: That an algebra is also a
-system is clear:
for all
.
For a set in a d-system
, its complement
is also in
. So, for a decreasing sequence
, writing
shows that
is also a monotone class.
Now, suppose that is a
-algebra. For any
, define a sequence
by
and
for
. Then,
is in
, so
is an algebra and, hence, also a
-system. Next,
for all
. So
is a d-system and, hence, also a monotone class. ⬜
The definitions above are also related by the following equivalent characterizations of -algebras.
Lemma 3 For a collection
of subsets of
, the following are equivalent.
is a
-algebra.
is both a
-system and a d-system.
is both an algebra and a monotone class.
Proof: Lemma 2 states that a -algebra is also a
-system, an algebra, a monotone class, and a d-system. Only the converse statements remain.
Suppose that is both an algebra and a monotone class. If
is a sequence in
then each finite union
is also in
. As
is increasing, the union
is in
, which is therefore a
-algebra.
Suppose that is both a
-system and a d-system. By the d-system property,
for all
. Hence,
for
, showing that
is an algebra. It is also monotone class, by the second statement of lemma 2. Hence,
is a
-algebra. ⬜
By definition, measures are constructed with respect to a -algebra on a set
. Precisely, a measure
satisfies countable additivity
for sequences of pairwise disjoint sets in
. In some sense, it would be more natural to define measures on d-systems rather than
-algebras. This is because any extension of a probability measure from a collection of sets
to the d-system it generates is unique, by the identities
(1) |
Here, and
is an increasing sequence of sets. For
-algebras, this does not hold. The measures of
and
cannot, in general, be determined just from the measures of
and
. However, only using d-systems would be much too restrictive. Finite unions and intersections are very simple set operations under which we would want the class of measurable sets should be closed. This is where the
-system lemma comes in. So long as we start from a
-system, then the d-system that it generates is already a
-algebra.
Given any collection of subsets of a set
, we refer to the smallest
-algebra containing
as the
-algebra generated by
, and is denoted by
. Similarly, we can talk about the
-system, algebra, monotone class, or d-system generated by
. The following result is known variously as the
-system lemma, Dynkin’s
–
theorem, or even as the monotone class theorem.
Theorem 4 (Dynkin) Let
be a
-system on a set
, and
be a d-system containing
. Then,
.
In particular, if
is the d-system generated by
, then
.
Proof: First, suppose that is the d-system generated by
. As
-algebras are also d-systems, the inequality
is immediate. Only the reverse inequality needs to be shown.
For any , let
denote the collection of sets
satisfying
. If
are in
, we have
so . Next, supposing that
is an increasing sequence in
,
so . This shows that
is itself a d-system
For , the
-system property immediately gives
, so
. Then, for any
and
, we have
or, equivalently,
. This, again, shows that
. Hence,
. Therefore,
for all
. We have shown that
is a
-system and, by lemma 3, is a
-algebra. So,
, giving
as required.
Finally, let be any d-system containing
. If
is the d-system generated by
then,
as required. ⬜
As an immediate application of the -system lemma, we show uniqueness of extensions of measures.
Lemma 5 Let
and
be probability measures on a measurable space
. If they agree on a
-system generating
, then
.
Proof: Let be the set of
for which
. By equations (1) applied to
and
,
is a d-system. As it also contains a
-system generating the
-algebra
, theorem 4 gives
, so
on
. ⬜
The cumulative distribution function of a probability measure
on the Borel sigma algebra on the real line is defined by
. A common use of the above lemma is the following.
Corollary 6 A probability measure on the standard Borel space on the real line is uniquely determined by its distribution function.
Proof: The standard Borel space is , where
is the Borel
-algebra on
. Let
consist of the intervals
for
. This is a
-system with
. If
and
are two finite measures with the same distribution function, then
for all
. So
and
agree on
. Lemma 5 gives
. ⬜
I move on to the statement of the monotone class theorem. Here, we weaken the requirements on so that it is only required to be a monotone class, rather than the more restrictive d-system requirement used by the
-system lemma. This is at the expense of requiring the stronger condition that
is an algebra, and not just a
-system.
Theorem 7 (Monotone Class Theorem) Let
be an algebra on a set
, and
be a monotone class containing
. Then,
.
In particular, if
is the monotone class generated by
, then
.
In many cases where the monotone class theorem is used, the collection of sets that we start with almost, but not quite, satisfies the definition of an algebra. For example, if it is the closed subsets of a metrizable space, then
is closed under finite intersections and unions. The complement of a closed set need not be closed, although it is always the limit of an increasing sequence of closed sets. For such cases, the following slightly generalized version can be useful. Note that theorem 7 is an immediate consequence.
We use the notation for the monotone class generated by a collection
of subsets of a set
.
Theorem 8 (Monotone Class Theorem) Let
be a nonempty collections of subsets of
such that
and
are in
for all
. Then,
.
In particular, if
is a monotone class containing
then,
.
Proof: As -algebras are also monotone classes, the inequality
is immediate. Only the reverse inequality needs to be shown. Let
be the collection of
such that
is also in
. By the condition of the theorem,
. If
is an increasing sequence then, by the monotone class property,
and
are both in . So,
is in
, showing that it is closed under taking limits of increasing sequences. Similarly, it is closed under taking limits of decreasing sequences so is a monotone class, giving
. Therefore,
for all
.
Now, for any , let
denote the collection of
such that
is also in
. For any sequence
,
So, if is an increasing or decreasing sequence, its limit is also in
, showing that
is a monotone class. By the condition of the theorem,
for any
, giving
. Hence,
for all
and
. This shows that
for any
. Therefore,
, showing that
is closed under pairwise intersections.
We have shown that is closed under set complements and pairwise intersections. As it is nonempty, this shows that it is an algebra. By lemma 3, it is a
-algebra, giving
as required. ⬜
I had some trouble with the last part (starting with “For
, the
-system property…” of the proof of theorem 4 and it took me a while to figure out the exact mechanics of the arguments. I am proposing a slightly extended explanation below. You can of course completely ignore this but maybe some readers would profit from a slightly more detailed explanation.
For
, the
-system property immediately gives
. Note first that by definition of
, we have
for any
.
As
is the minimal d-system generated by
and
is another d-system, we obtain
, which already implies
, but so far only for
.
Now consider more generally
and additionally an
. Because of what we just established, we know that
, i.e.
, which just means that
. By symmetry, this implies
, thus (because
was arbitrary),
. By the same argument as above (minimality of the d-system
), this again yields
, this time for all
.
This statement implies that for all
, we know that
, i.e.
, which is the definition of
being a
-system. By lemma 3 (make link),
is also a
-algebra.
[Rest as in the text]
Thanks for your suggestion. I will have a reread through the argument when I have some time, and update accordingly.
The link to Borel is broken.
I meant the first hyperlink to Borel sets.
Fixed. Thanks!
Hello!
First of all, you have an amazing blog, thank you very much for your work!
Apart from that, I have some trouble with the proof of Theorem 8.
Basically, we take a monotone class generated by E and prove that it is closed under intersections and complements. However, as far as I understand, one feature is still missing: it is never mentioned that the set E belongs to the corresponding monotone class. In Theorem 7 it holds automatically (due to E being an algebra), but how can we say that E is in M(E)?
Thank you in advance!
I showed that
is closed under set complementation and intersection. As it is nonempty, it contains at least one set A and hence contains
.
Suppose $m$ is defined on $\mathcal{E} \subset \mathcal{P}(E)$ and $m(E) < \infty$. It is possible to show if $m_1,m_2$ are two extensions from $\mathcal{E}$ to $\lambda(\mathcal{E})$ then they must be equal, but does an extension exist like it does in in the algebra to $\sigma$-algebra case?
Although the Caratheodory Measurable set condition doesn't work anymore, from $(1)$ it seems $m$ can be constructed iteratively from $\mathcal{E}$ to $\lambda{E}$.